Results for 'S. I. Rosenberg'

980 found
Order:
  1. On the Tits alternative for a class of finitely presented groups with a special focus on symbolic computations.Anja I. S. Moldenhauer, Gerhard Rosenberger & Kristina Rosenthal - 2016 - In Delaram Kahrobaei, Bren Cavallo & David Garber (eds.), Algebra and computer science. Providence, Rhode Island: American Mathematical Society.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  78
    ‘I Thinks’: Some Reflections on Kant's Paralogisms.Jay F. Rosenberg - 1986 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10 (1):503-530.
  3. What Rosenberg's philosophy of economics is not.Alexander Rosenberg - 1986 - Philosophy of Science 53 (1):127-132.
    Douglas W. Hands's “What Economics Is Not: An Economist's Response to Rosenberg“ is an unsympathetic criticism of the explanatory hypotheses of “If Economics Isn't Science, What Is It?”. Before replying to his objection, I summarize the claims of that paper.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  4.  35
    Beyond the code of ethics: the responsibility of professional societies.Richard S. Rosenberg - 1998 - Acm Sigcas Computers and Society 28 (2):18-25.
    Drafting a code of ethics for a professional society is a daunting and exhausting task. Whereas the basic components of a professional code of ethics or professional standards are reasonably well understood, the specific details require careful tailoring to meet the needs of a given profession. The difficulty of this process probably explains why such codes are rarely updated. Furthermore, once having produced an updated ethics code, many professional organizations, or perhaps better the associated executive, feel that their work has (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  34
    Husserl’s Fifth Cartesian Meditation and the Appresentation of the Other in Sport.Danny Rosenberg - 2021 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 16 (4):526-543.
    This paper examines a single relevant source regarding Edmund Husserl’s transcendental phenomenology and his attempt to explain how we perceive and experience the Other. In the fifth chapter of the Cartesian Meditations, Husserl describes our encounters with others through a process of non-inferential analogy and details the ways we ‘appresent’ the Other. This unique and admittedly narrow approach to understanding intersubjectivity, I submit, offers significant insights regarding the nature of interactions between competing athletes and the meanings these experiences generate. The (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  71
    Wittgenstein's Theory of Language as Picture.Jay F. Rosenberg - 1968 - American Philosophical Quarterly 5 (1):18 - 30.
    I develop one account of propositions as pictures sharing logical form with what they depict. Two concepts of simplicity in the "tractatus" are then isolated. Since characterization of sachverhalten as configurations of referential simples does not entail their inferential simplicity, By rejecting the tractarian theory of inference, I retain the picture theory without commitment to atomistic ontology. Interpretation of inference as performance then gives rise to a second sense of picturing.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7. Making mechanism interesting.Alex Rosenberg - 2018 - Synthese 195 (1):11-33.
    I note the multitude of ways in which, beginning with the classic paper by Machamer et al., the mechanists have qualify their methodological dicta, and limit the vulnerability of their claims by strategic vagueness regarding their application. I go on to generalize a version of the mechanist requirement on explanations due to Craver and Kaplan :601–627, 2011) in cognitive and systems neuroscience so that it applies broadly across the life sciences in accordance with the view elaborated by Craver and Darden (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  8. How is biological explanation possible?Alex Rosenberg - 2001 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 52 (4):735-760.
    That biology provides explanations is not open to doubt. But how it does so must be a vexed question for those who deny that biology embodies laws or other generalizations with the sort of explanatory force that the philosophy of science recognizes. The most common response to this problem has involved redefining law so that those grammatically general statements which biologists invoke in explanations can be counted as laws. But this terminological innovation cannot identify the source of biology's explanatory power. (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  9.  46
    On variational cross-examination: a method for postphenomenological multistability.Robert Rosenberger - 2023 - AI and Society 38 (6):2229-2242.
    How should we understand postphenomenological methodology? Postphenomenology is a research perspective which builds on phenomenological and pragmatist philosophy to explore human–technology relations, but one with open methodological questions. Here, I offer some thoughts on the epistemological processes that should be (and often implicitly may be) at work in this research. In particular, I am concerned with postphenomenological research on technological “multistability,” i.e., a device’s ever-present capacity to be used for a variety of purposes, and to always be meaningful in multiple (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  10. Still Mythic After All Those Years: On Alston’s Latest Defense of the Given.Jay F. Rosenberg - 2006 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (1):157-173.
    Wilfrid Sellars' conclusion in "Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind" that "the Given" is a "Myth" quickly elicited philosophical opposition and remains contentious fifty years later. William Alston has challenged that conclusion on several occasions by attempting to devise an acceptable account of perception committed to the givenness of perceived objects. His most recent challenge advances a "Theory of Appearing" which posits irreducible non-conceptual relations, ostensibly overlooked by Sellars, e.g., of "looking red", between the subject and the object perceived, that (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  11. Naturalistic epistemology for eliminative materialists.Alex Rosenberg - 1999 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (2):335-358.
    This paper defends and extends Quine’s version of a naturalistic epistemology, and defends it against criticism, especially that offered by Kim, according to which Quine’s naturalism deprives epistemology of its normative role, and indeed of its relevance to psychological states, such as beliefs, whose warrant epistemology aims to assess. I defend Quinean epistemology’s objections to the epistemic pluralism associated with other self-styled naturalistic epistemologies, and show how recent theories in the philosophy of psychology which fail to account for the intentionality (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  12. Why do Spatiotemporally Restricted Regularities Explain in the Social Sciences?Alex Rosenberg - 2012 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 63 (1):1-26.
    Employing a well-known local regularity from macroeconomics, the Phillips curve, I examine Woodward’s ([2000], [2003]) account of the explanatory power of such historically restricted generalizations and the mathematical models with which they are sometimes associated. The article seeks to show that, pace Woodward, to be explanatory such generalizations need to be underwritten by more fundamental ones, and that rational choice theory would not avail in this case to provide the required underwriting. Examining how such explanatory restricted regularities are underwritten in (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  13.  99
    Why Social Science is Biological Science.Alex Rosenberg - 2017 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 48 (3):341-369.
    The social sciences need to take seriously their status as divisions of biology. As such they need to recognize the central role of Darwinian processes in all the phenomena they seek to explain. An argument for this claim is formulated in terms of a small number of relatively precise premises that focus on the nature of the kinds and taxonomies of all the social sciences. The analytical taxonomies of all the social sciences are shown to require a Darwinian approach to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  14. First-Order Representationalist Panqualityism.Harry Rosenberg - forthcoming - Erkenntnis:1-16.
    Panqualityism, recently defended by Sam Coleman, is a variety of Russellian monism on which the categorical properties of fundamental physical entities are qualities, or, in Coleman’s exposition, unconscious qualia. Coleman defends a quotationalist, higher-order thought version of panqualityism. The aim of this paper is, first, to demonstrate that a first-order representationalist panqualityism is also available, and to argue positively in its favor. For it shall become apparent that quotationalist and first-order representationalist panqualityism are, in spite of their close similarities, radically (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  67
    But, That’s Not Phenomenology!Robert Rosenberger - 2020 - Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology 24 (1-2):83-113.
    A discussion is emerging within the contemporary philosophy of technology over issues of discrimination through design. My suggestion is that a productive way to approach this topic is through a combination of insights from the postphenomenological and critical constructivist perspectives. In particular, I recommend that we build on the postphenomenological notion of “multistability” and conceive of instances of discrimination through design as a kind of discriminatory “stability,” one possible instantiation of a device that could be usefully contrasted with others. Through (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  16. On the Intrinsic Nature of the Physical.Gregg H. Rosenberg - 1999 - In Stuart R. Hameroff, Alfred W. Kaszniak & A. C. Scott (eds.), Toward a Science of Consciousness III. MIT Press.
    In its original context Hawking was writing about the significance of physics for questions about God's existence and responsibility for creation. I am co-opting the sentiment for another purpose, though. As stated Hawking could equally be directing the question at concerns about the seemingly abstract information physics conveys about the world, and the full body of facts contained in the substance of the world. Would even a complete and adequate physics tell us all the general facts about the stuff the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17. Comments on Bechtel, levels of description and explanation in cognitive science.Jay F. Rosenberg - 1994 - Minds and Machines 4 (1):27-37.
    I begin by tracing some of the confusions regarding levels and reduction to a failure to distinguish two different principles according to which theories can be viewed as hierarchically arranged — epistemic authority and ontological constitution. I then argue that the notion of levels relevant to the debate between symbolic and connectionist paradigms of mental activity answers to neither of these models, but is rather correlative to the hierarchy of functional decompositions of cognitive tasks characteristic of homuncular functionalism. Finally, I (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18. Husserl's Missing Multistability.Robert Rosenberger - 2016 - Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology 20 (2):153-167.
    The notion of “multistability” is a central fixture of the postphenomenological framework of thought, one of the central ideas that enables this perspective to avoid both shallow determinism and instrumentalism. While this notion has been put to use in numerous case studies and theoretical treatments, here I argue that the work of following out the philosophical implications of technological multistability has only just begun. Don Ihde’s new book, Husserl’s Missing Technologies, provides a helpful jumping off point as he provides a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19.  60
    Principled Autonomy and Plagiarism.Melinda Rosenberg - 2011 - Journal of Academic Ethics 9 (1):61-69.
    Every semester, professors in every discipline are burdened with the task of checking for plagiarized papers. Since plagiarism has become rampant in the university, it can be argued that devoting time to checking for plagiarism is nothing more than a fool’s errand. Students will continue to plagiarize regardless of the consequences. In this paper, I will argue that professors do have a categorically binding obligation to confirm whether papers have been plagiarized. I will use Onora O'Neill’s account of principled autonomy (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  13
    One Ventilator Too Few?Noah Polzin-Rosenberg - 2018 - Hastings Center Report 48 (2):3-4.
    Sometimes it's better to be lucky than good. As new blood filled our young patient's veins, her breathing became regular and her pulse full. She was so far gone I would not have expected her to recover consciousness for a day, if at all, but within an hour, she began to wake up. We removed the breathing tube a couple of hours later— no ventilator ever needed.As life-sustaining technology becomes more widely available in fortunate parts of the developing world, benefits (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  71
    Privacy as a Matter of Taste and Right.Alexander Rosenberg - 2000 - Social Philosophy and Policy 17 (2):68.
    Privacy is something we all want. We seek privacy to prevent others from securing information about us that is immediately embarrassing, and so causes us pain but not material loss. We also value privacy for strategic reasons in order to prevent others from imposing material and perhaps psychic costs upon us. I use the expression “securing information” so that it covers everything from the immediate sensory data that a voyeur acquires to the financial data a rival may acquire about our (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  83
    Nietzsche, competition and athletic ability.Melinda Rosenberg - 2008 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 2 (3):274 – 284.
    The purpose of this paper is to examine the relationship between Friedrich Nietzsche's notion of the agon (Greek for contest) and the construction of athletic ability. In 'Homer's contest', Nietzsche claims that the ancient Greek agon was a contest that included only the most qualified competitors battling each other for honour and victory. Nietzsche seeks to restore the agon in contemporary society. Nietzsche believes that contests have lost this agonistic meaning since they are no more than contrived competitions between underqualified (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  23.  78
    Notes on a Nonfoundational Phenomenology of Technology.Robert Rosenberger - 2017 - Foundations of Science 22 (3):471-494.
    The emerging school of thought called “postphenomenology” offers a distinct understanding of the ways that people experience technology usage. This perspective combines insights from the philosophical tradition of phenomenology with commitments to the anti-essentialism and nonfoundationalism of American pragmatism. One of postphenomenology’s central positions is that technologies always remain “multistable,” i.e., subject to different uses and meanings. But I suggest that as this perspective matures, philosophical problems are emerging around the notion of multistability, what I call “the problem of invariance” (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  24. Reductionism in a historical science.Alex Rosenberg - 2001 - Philosophy of Science 68 (2):135-163.
    Reductionism is a metaphysical thesis, a claim about explanations, and a research program. The metaphysical thesis reductionists advance (and antireductionists accept) is that all facts, including all biological facts, are fixed by the physical and chemical facts; there are no non-physical events, states, or processes, and so biological events, states and processes are “nothing but” physical ones. The research program can be framed as a methodological prescription which follows from the claim about explanations. Antireductionism does not dispute reductionism’s metaphysical claim, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  25.  82
    Kant and the problem of simultaneous causation.Jay F. Rosenberg - 1998 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 6 (2):167 – 188.
    The argument of Kant's Second Analogy provides only for causal connections between successive appearances, but, as Kant himself immediately notes, in many cases cause and effect are simultaneous. This essay examines Kant's solution to the resulting problem of simultaneous causation. I argue that there are, in fact, at least two distinct problems falling together under the rubric 'simultaneous causation', both reflecting significant features of paradigmatic causal-explanatory scenarios within Newtonian mechanics - a problem about the 'persisting simultaneity' of a continuous or (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  52
    Mediating Mars: Perceptual Experience and Scientific Imaging Technologies. [REVIEW]Robert Rosenberger - 2013 - Foundations of Science 18 (1):75-91.
    The philosophical tradition of phenomenology, with its focus on human bodily perception, can be used to explore the ways scientific instrumentation shapes a user’s experience. Building on Don Ihde’s account of technological embodiment, I develop a framework of concepts for articulating the experience of image interpretation in science. These concepts can be of practical value to the analysis of scientific debates over image interpretation for the ways they draw out the relationships between the image-making processes and the rival scientific explanations (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  27.  50
    Synonymy and the epistemology of linguistics.Jay F. Rosenberg - 1967 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 10 (1-4):405-420.
    In Word and Object, Quine argues from the observation that ?there is no justification for collating linguistic meanings, unless in terms of men's dispositions to respond overtly to socially observable stimulations? to the conclusion that ?the enterprise of translation is found to be involved in a certain systematic indeterminacy?. In this paper, I propose to show (1) that Quine's thesis, when properly understood, reveals in the situation of translation no peculiar indeterminacy but merely the ordinary indeterminacy present in any case (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  20
    How to Talk about Pigs.Jay Rosenberg - 1974 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 3 (3):389 - 403.
    It has been about 20 years since Austin offered to teach us some simple ways of talking. In view of the attention paid the balance of the Austin corpus, this offer has been greeted with a surprising silence. There are, perhaps, some reasons for this lack of response. First, of course, the article is a difficult one, tortuous and opaque. Second, I suspect that there is a general, though tacit, consensus that any insights of value in “How To Talk” have (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. The Posited Self: The Non-Theistic Foundation in Kierkegaard’s Writings.Rasmus Rosenberg Larsen - 2015 - Kierkegaard Studies Yearbook 20 (1):31-54.
    We may correctly say that Søren Kierkegaard is one of the most influential Christian-religious thinkers of the modern era, but are we equally justified in categorizing his writings as foundationally religious? This paper challenges a prevailing exclusive-theological interpretation that contends that Kierkegaard principally writes from a Christian dogmatic viewpoint. I argue that Kierkegaard’s religion is better understood as an outcome of his philosophical analysis of human nature. Conclusively, we should appreciate Kierkegaard first as a philosopher, whose aim is the explication (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30. The mind and its expression.Jay Rosenberg - unknown
    Remarks such as 'I am in pain' and 'I think that it's raining' present opportunity for reflection and theory. Ostensibly such remarks report what one feels or thinks. But we do not in conversation treat these remarks as we do ordinary reports. If I ask you about the weather and you say, "I think it's raining," I can't complain that you told me just about your thoughts, and not about the weather. It is often held, moreover, when we do take (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Comments and criticism on multiple realization and the special sciences.Alex Rosenberg - manuscript
    It is widely held that disciplines are autonomous when their taxonomies are “substrate neutral” and when the events, states and processes that realize their descriptive vocabulary are heterogeneous. This will be particularly true in the case of disciplines whose taxonomy consists largely in terms that individuate by function. Having concluded that the multiple realization of functional kinds is far less widespread than assumed or argued for, Shapiro cannot avail himself of the argument for the autonomy of the special sciences which (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32. Identity and substance in Hume and Kant.Jay F. Rosenberg - 2000 - Topoi 19 (2):137-145.
    According to Hume, the idea of a persisting, self-identical object, distinct from our impressions of it, and the idea of a duration of time, the mere passage of time without change, are mutually supporting "fictions". Each rests upon a "mistake", the commingling of "qualities of the imagination" or "impressions of reflection" with "external" impressions (perceptions), and, strictly speaking, we are conceptually and epistemically entitled to neither. Among Kant's aims in the First Critique is the securing of precisely these entitlements. Like (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  33.  47
    Some comment's on Rosenberg's review.Elliott Sober - 1996 - Philosophy of Science 63 (3):465-469.
    I am grateful to Philip Kitcher for inviting me to comment on Alexander Rosenberg's (1996) review of Philosophy of Biology (Sober 1993) and to Rosenberg for his kind words about my book at the very beginning and the very end of his review. However, I cannot help feeling that most of the material in Rosenberg's review describes a different book from the one I wrote. Of the four philosophical claims that he ascribes to me, only one of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34.  23
    A Case Study in the Applied Philosophy of Imaging: The Synaptic Vesicle Debate.Robert Rosenberger - 2011 - Science, Technology, and Human Values 36 (1):6-32.
    Thinkers from a variety of fields analyze the roles of imaging technologies in science and consider their implications for many issues, from our conception of selfhood to the authority of science. In what follows, I encourage scholars to develop an applied philosophy of imaging, that is, to collect these analyses of scientific imaging and to reflect on how they can be made useful for ongoing scientific work. As an example of this effort, I review concepts developed in Don Ihde’s phenomenology (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  35.  11
    Eliciting Deviation.Daniel Rosenberg - 2019 - Chiasmi International 21:225-238.
    In his discussions on literature, Merleau-Ponty often turns to the notion of deviation as a constitutive principle of literary language. Deviation indicates the capacity of a literary work to transgress against its own limits and to offer an experience of otherness, or alterity. This alterity is not given in the work, but is constituted by the recipient through the more visceral and physical aspects of literary language. The recipient of the work thus adopts a second voice: that of the author (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Russell versus Steiner on physics and causality.Alexander Rosenberg - 1989 - Philosophy of Science 56 (2):341-347.
    In "Events and Causality" Mark Steiner argues that though Bertrand Russell was right to claim that the laws of physics do not express causal relations, nevertheless, Russell was wrong to suppose that therefore causality plays no role in physics. I argue that Steiner misses the point of Russell's argument for the first of these claims, and because of this Steiner's argument against the second fails to controvert it. Steiner fails to see that Russell's argument against causation, is in fact an (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  62
    Selection and science: Critical notice of David Hull's science as a process. [REVIEW]Alex Rosenberg - 1992 - Biology and Philosophy 7 (2):217-228.
    An examination of Hull's claims about the nature of interactors, replicators and selection, with special attention to how the genetic material realizes the first two types, and a critique of Hull's attempt to apply the theory of natural selection to the explanation of scientific change, and in particular the succession of theories. I conclude that difficulties attending the molecular instantiation of Hull's theory are vastly increased when it comes to be applied to memes.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  38.  61
    A Phenomenology of Image Use in Science.Robert Rosenberger - 2011 - Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology 15 (2):156-169.
    Insights from the phenomenological tradition of philosophy can be fruitfully applied to ongoing scientific investigations. In what follows, I review and refine a methodology I have developed for the application of concepts from the phenomenology of technology—concepts which articulate bodily and perceptual relations to technology—to a specific context of scientific practice: debate over the interpretation of laboratory images. As a guiding example, I introduce a case study of a contemporary debate over images of Mars which reveal evidence of fluid movement (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  39.  54
    The Spatial Experience of Telephone Use.Robert Rosenberger - 2010 - Environment, Space, Place 2 (2):63-77.
    Ideas developed within the philosophical tradition of phenomenology can be used to describe the experience of talking on the phone. In particular, I build on a contemporary brand of phenomenology called “postphenomenology,” a school of thought which specializes in the analysis of the relationships that form between users and technologies. Three central concepts are reviewed and developed: transparency, sedimentation, and what I call “field composition.” These concepts can be used for the description of the way that the content of a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  29
    Speaking Lions.Jay F. Rosenberg - 1977 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 (1):155 - 160.
    “If a lion could speak, we could not understand him.”Well, why not, for heaven's sake? A speech impediment, perhaps. Imagine a cross between a severe lisp and a roar. That would be difficult to understand. But not impossible. The claim is that we could not understand him. Very well, who are we?Perhaps we are the English speakers. Of course what we could understand would depend upon which language the lion spoke. I couldn't understand him, for example, if he spoke in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. “Doubts about receptivity”, commentary on G. Rosenberg's a place for consciousness (oxford U. P., 2004).William S. Robinson - 2006 - PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 12 (5).
    Abstract: Receptivity is a foundational concept in the analysis of causation given in Gregg Rosenberg’s A Place for Consciousness and it enters, directly or indirectly, into the definitions of a host of other terms in the book. This commentary raises a problem (which I call “the triviality problem”) about how we are to understand receptivity. Search for a solution proceeds by examination of several contexts in which the concept of receptivity is used. Although a satisfactory solution remains elusive, it (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Kierkegaard, Eve and Metaphors of Births. [REVIEW]Rasmus Rosenberg Larsen - forthcoming - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology:1-3.
    Alison Assiter has put together a work that has the potential to create an exciting and stimulating debate in Kierkegaard circles. Mostly because she portrays Kierkegaard as an idealist ontologist, that is, a philosopher of not just human nature (i.e. subjectivity), but also nature in its cosmic totality. Thus, what I find most admirable is that with Assiter we have a thinker who has the philosophical courage to suggest that the purported relationship between Schelling and Kierkegaard leads necessarily to bold (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  15
    Comments on Rosenberg's Review.Elliott Sober - 1986 - Behavior and Philosophy 14 (1):89.
    Long ago, my undergraduate advisor counseled me against “replying to reviews.” Alexander Rosenberg cannot be blamed for tempting me to disregard this advice, since his review of my book, The Nature of Selection, is a generous one. However, the editors of this journal invited me to comment and this proved to be more temptation than I could withstand. In what follows, I take up some of the main themes that Rosenberg discusses and try to clarify those issues that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44.  46
    Multiple Realizability and Biological Laws.Jani P. Raerinne & Markus I. Eronen - 2012 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 34 (4):521-537.
    We critically analyze Alexander Rosenberg’s argument based on the multiple realizability of biological properties that there are no biological laws. The argument is intuitive and suggestive. Nevertheless, a closer analysis reveals that the argument rests on dubious assumptions about the nature of natural selection, laws of nature, and multiple realizability. We also argue that the argument is limited in scope, since it applies to an outmoded account of laws and the applicability of the argument to other more promising accounts (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  45. Kant, Rosenberg, and the Mirror of Philosophy.Willem deVries - 2010 - In James R. O'Shea & Eric M. Rubenstein (eds.), Self, Language, and World: Problems from Kant, Sellars, and Rosenberg. Ridgeview Publishing Co..
    The "Transcendental Deduction" in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason is one of the great mirrors of philosophy. By that I mean that there seems to be no steady and unchanging image to be found in that text; each philosopher who approaches it finds in it a reflection of his or her own deepest concerns. Jay Rosenberg's new book, "Accessing Kant: A Relaxed Introduction to the Critique of Pure Reason" is no exception. Rosenberg lays out a different approach to (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Rosenberg, reducibility and consciousness.William E. Seager - 2006 - PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 12.
    Rosenberg’s general argumentative strategy in favour of panpsychism is an extension of a traditional pattern. Although his argument is complex and intricate, I think a model that is historically significant and fundamentally similar to the position Rosenberg advances might help us understand the case for panpsychism. Thus I want to begin by considering a Leibnizian argument for panpsychism.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47. Function attribution depends on the explanatory context: A Reply to Neander and Rosenberg's Reply to Nanay.Bence Nanay - 2012 - Journal of Philosophy 109 (10):623-627.
    In ‘A modal theory of function’, I gave an argument against all existing theories of function and outlined a new theory. Karen Neander and Alex Rosenberg argue against both my negative and my positive claim. My aim here is not merely to defend my account from their objections, but to (a) very briefly point out that the new account of etiological function they propose in response to my criticism cannot avoid the circularity worry either and, more importantly, to (b) (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  48. Are Clusters Races? A Discussion of the Rhetorical Appropriation of Rosenberg et al.’s “Genetic Structure of Human Populations”.Melissa Wills - 2017 - Philosophy, Theory, and Practice in Biology 9 (12).
    Noah Rosenberg et al.'s 2002 article “Genetic Structure of Human Populations” reported that multivariate genomic analysis of a large cell line panel yielded reproducible groupings (clusters) suggestive of individuals' geographical origins. The paper has been repeatedly cited as evidence that traditional notions of race have a biological basis, a claim its authors do not make. Critics of this misinterpretation have often suggested that it follows from interpreters' personal biases skewing the reception of an objective piece of scientific writing. I (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  49.  7
    Kommunikat︠s︡ii︠a︡ i obrazovanie.S. I. Dudnik (ed.) - 2004 - Sankt-Peterburg: Sankt-Peterburgskoe filosofskoe ob-vo.
  50.  57
    Reply to Rosenberg.Peter Godfrey-Smith - 2018 - Biology and Philosophy 33 (3-4):19.
    I respond to two of the main arguments in Rosenberg’s commentary on “Mind, Matter, and Metabolism.” Rosenberg’s claim that metabolic activities are “modularized” in a way that sets them apart from cognitive processes is not true given the broad sense of the “metabolic” employed in my paper, and contemporary neuroscience, including the work on navigation cited by Rosenberg, has begun to yield an understanding of subjectivity and “point of view.”.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 980